1,823
Views
0
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Introduction

Social Indicators of Trust in the Age of Informational Chaos

ORCID Icon & ORCID Icon

ABSTRACT

Expert knowledge regularly informs personal and civic-decision making. To decide which experts to trust, lay publics —including policymakers and experts from other domains—use different epistemic and non-epistemic cues. Epistemic cues such as honesty, like when experts are forthcoming about conflicts of interest, are a popular way of understanding how people evaluate and decide which experts to trust. However, many other epistemic cues, like the evidence supporting information from experts, are inaccessible to lay publics. Therefore, lay publics simultaneously use second-order social cues in their environment to inform decisions to trust. These second-order social cues, or ‘social indicators of trust’, prevent lay publics from having to trust blindly. Social indicators of trust therefore inform lay publics’ epistemic vigilance, or constant low level-monitoring of testimony from experts. This special issue examines the nature, acquisition and application of social indicators of trust for scientific experts and institutions. It also raises questions about the types of trust asked of lay publics and challenges traditional normative assumptions about the relationship between science and lay publics through study of attitudes, values, and experiences. The issue descriptively re-examines the structure of institutions, their role and methods for ferrying information, as well as how social indicators operate in times of crisis. In this collection of works, we bridge history, science, philosophy of science, science and technology studies, science communication and social epistemology, to broaden the discourse on trust in experts and more accurately reflect the imperfect yet indispensable endeavour that trusting is.

Experts communicate invaluable information for lay publics’ personal and civic decision-making. Expertise is present everywhere in contemporary societies and influences the way we vote, eat, take care of our health and move freely (or not) in our cities. It is thus crucial that our trust in experts is reliable and grounded on a rational basis. But how do lay publics decide which experts to trust when they lack the competence to evaluate the information provided? What additional information is available and how do we use it to assess expertise? This special issue explores social indicators of trust, or cues in our social environment that provide supplementary information that people consciously and unconsciously use to decide which experts to trust.

‘Social indicators’ are best known as an area of study in sociology that originated in the 1960s as a quality of life assessment tool in the United States.Footnote1 At the time, the most popular definition was that published by the United States Department of Health’s Toward a Social Report which defined social indicators as ‘a statistic of direct normative interest which facilitates concise, comprehensive and balanced judgments about the condition of major aspects of a society’. (United States Department of Health, Education, and Welfare Citation1969, 97) This definition was quickly criticized for being too restrictive (Sheldon and Freeman Citation1970) and was subsequently broadened to include components of a social system model ‘including sociopsychological, economic, demographic, and ecological’ dimensions (Land Citation1971, 323). These components can be accumulated into a time-series and can therefore be aggregated or disaggregated for the purpose of monitoring the social system, ‘helping to identify changes and to guide intervention to alter the course of social change’ (Ferriss Citation1988, 601).

There is a diversity of social indicators to be measured. For example, education levels, public perceptions of corruption, household income, suicide rates and charitable donations are all social indicators that help to understand the state of society. As a consequence of their breath, throughout their five decades of study, the ‘social indicators movement’ has generated philosophical, methodological and empirical studies leading to improvements in social measurement, reporting, accounting and gauging of well-being (Ferriss Citation1988). The literature has considered different topologies and various social realities reflecting understanding of phenomena that are increasingly complex, interrelated, interactive and dynamic. For example, in the face of change, uncertainty and risk, normative, descriptive and predictive questions about how to establish and measure sustainable well-being are becoming an area of increased attention (Land and Michalos Citation2018).

Our socio-epistemological account of social indicators examines the selection of social cues by lay publics as opposed to researchers. We consider structural signals like hierarchical organisation, conversational signs like the confidence of interlocutors, and reputational cues like an expert’s influence which lay publics use to inform their epistemic vigilance, or constant low-level monitoring of testimony (Sperber et al. Citation2010). What sociological social indicators of well-being and socio-epistemological social indicators of trust have in common – besides attention to publics, their diversity, and experience in the world – is that both types of indicators share an important relationship to trust. Traditional social indicators investigate trust as an indicator of well-being (Bäck and Serup Christensen Citation2016; Awaworyi Churchill and Mishra Citation2017), while the forthcoming works show how lay publics use social indicators to decide which experts to trust.

In both the original approach to social indicators of trust and ours, thin or generalized trust is regarded as the beliefs people hold about how others, particularly those they do not know, will act towards them (Uslaner Citation2002; Delhey and Newton Citation2005; Nannestad Citation2008). It can range from harm at worst to taking the interests of others into account at best (Delhey and Newton Citation2003). Generalized trust has the pragmatic value of acting as glue to facilitate and sustain social ties between increasingly diverse individuals and groups, for example, to help them overcome collective problems (Fukuyama Citation1995). Thus, generalized trust is taken to be an indicator of social cohesion, societal function and social capital (Putnam Citation2000).

Higher levels of generalized trust are correlated with individual and societal level benefits. For individuals, it is associated with better financial and educational outcomes, more civic engagement, and better health (e.g. Putnam Citation2000; Delhey and Newton Citation2003; Nakhaie and Arnold Citation2010; Dauner, Wilmot, and Schultz Citation2015). On a societal level, generalized trust coincides with lower crime rates, more economic growth, and more effective governance (e.g. Knack and Keefer Citation1997; Ritzen, Easterly, and Woolcock Citation2000; Messner, Richard Rosenfield, and Eric Citation2004). Because generalized trust is crucial to the social and economic prosperity of individuals, communities, and democratic functioning, it deserves to be understood in terms of how it can be fostered and maintained (Sturgis et al. Citation2012).Footnote2

Trust engages our emotions, cognitive abilities and social competences whether we are aware of it or not. The need for trust is also ubiquitous. We believe more than we can ever fully verify or be informed about, so we trust that experts will provide us reliable information. The inter and intra-personal dimensions of trust, and the conditions under which we extend trust, are increasingly being discussed by psychologists, sociologists, communicators and philosophers. In the philosophical literature, much of the interest in trust stems from Baier’s (Citation1986) work ‘Trust and Antitrust’. Here trust is articulated as a triadic relationship where a trustor (A) trusts the trustee (B) regarding some object, action, task or service (C) (236). A trusts B with respect to C where only the trustworthiness of B is a characteristic property. Though the trustworthiness of A might also be considered on moral and epistemic grounds, the cognitive evaluative tools that A uses to decide to trust B will be the focus of the following works.

Baier’s account of trust has prompted further research investigating the relationship between trust and reliance (Holton Citation1994; Wilholt Citation2013; Koskinen Citation2020; John Citation2020). After all, we (A) similarly rely on the relied (B) regarding some object, action, task or service (C). However, Baier underscores the normative dimensions of trust arguing that it generates different kinds of expectations, reactive attitudes and commitments compared to reliance. For instance, feelings of betrayal occur when trust is broken in contrast to the mere disappointment which one feels when the relied upon does not come through. Trust distinguishes itself from reliance by emphasising a sense of goodwill towards the trustor (Holton Citation1994), putting the trustor in a vulnerable position from which to morally appraise the trustee. This is not to say that trust and reliance are entirely separate entities as most philosophers view trust as a species of reliance but, with some separation between the two, we are able to explore examples of reliance without trust and trust without reliance.

By investigating how social indicators of trust apply to experts, this work examines the moral and epistemic reasoning that go into trust as it pertains to expertise. Epistemic trust is a disposition to believe that (B) will give us true information (C) in a situation where we are cognitively or socially vulnerable to the risk of false information (Origgi Citation2004). In other words, lay public community stakeholders (e.g. citizens, policymakers) have a disposition to believe that experts will provide them with reliable information because as non-experts they are in a epistemically vulnerable position. This is not to say that lay publics must trust passively: given their diverse knowledges and experiences, lay publics can (in some cases) access evidence to evaluate experts’ beliefs. However, it is difficult (if not impossible) to do this for all one’s beliefs.Footnote3

The epistemic asymmetry between experts and lay publics with respect to trust is especially evident for trust in scientific experts. Trust in scientific experts is based on a degree of epistemic dependence. In general, lay publics lack all or some of the premises from which experts reason to their conclusions, are in an epistemically inferior position to assess the support between expert premises and conclusions, and are ignorant of many or most counter-arguments (Hardwig Citation1985). From a political perspective, this asymmetry can cause tension between the need for science advice and the disregard for that advice in democratic policy-making (Gluckman and Wilsdon Citation2016). This is compounded by the ongoing debate about the appropriate normative position of science advisors within democratic governance (Doulgas Citation2021).

Scientific experts have specialized training and knowledge which allows them to assess evidence in attempt to establish truth. Part of their knowledge comes from holding more true beliefs or relying on a higher degree of true propositions and fewer beliefs in false propositions. Expert knowledge can also include an awareness of what other experts think about these propositions, an understanding of primary and secondary questions in the domain, and a set of skills or methods to apply this knowledge to new questions (Goldman Citation2001, 91–92)Footnote4. However, deciding to trust an expert does not determine which expert to trust. Where possible, experts can provide direct argumentative justification (or premises for epistemic beliefs) to support public evaluations of their trustworthiness. But given that this is not always possible, and assuming that there can be good reasons for believing experts besides factual reasons related to evidence, indirect argumentative justification including ‘second-order’ reasoning, is also used to determine which experts to trust.

Foundational work by Hardwig (Citation1985), Goldman (Citation2001) and Anderson (Citation2011) aims at establishing second-order criteria through which publics can evaluate indicators of expert trustworthiness. Hardwig (Citation1985) argues that these indicators can be used because it can be rational for lay publics not to ‘think for themselves’ and defer to experts. Goldman’s (Citation2001) argument-based evidence relies on five possible sources of trust in experts: arguments, agreement with consensus, appraisals by ‘meta-experts’, track-records, and interests or biases which can have second-order social cues. And Anderson (Citation2011) puts forward that any lay person with basic instruction and an internet connection can evaluate an expert’s competence and honesty to make up their mind about the expert’s trustworthiness.

Though the indicators Hardwig (Citation1985), Goldman (Citation2001) and Anderson (Citation2011) mention differ somewhat, epistemic authority (e.g. accreditation, recognition in the field), honesty (e.g. disclosing conflicts of interest), agreement with scientific consensus and epistemic responsibility (e.g. accountability to a community of inquirers, the peer-review process) are considered by the authors as ‘epistemic’ indicators. That is, these indicators rely on the cognitive abilities of publics to draw inferences from indirect information about the experts which can make a significant difference in the overall justification for accepting the truth of expert claims. What Hardwig (Citation1985), Goldman (Citation2001) and Anderson (Citation2011) provide with their epistemic criteria is close to derivative authority generated from lay peoples’ reasons for thinking that the source is in a good position to make the claim. In other words, that experts have enough knowledge to know the truth. However, people may not be familiar with scientometric indicators, like the number of citations or the H-index, and so they rely on other second-order indicators because in our interactions with experts we want to establish more than truth: we want to establish trust. That publics engage in trust relations with experts beyond the search for truth, can also help to explain the strong moral and emotional reactions that a breach of trust provokes in them.

Second-order social indicators of trust contribute to and are the product of social capital. Though defining social capital continues to be both a priority and a challenge (Ziersch et al. Citation2005; Sabatini Citation2015), it is referred to as all the ‘features of social life’ including networks, norms and values as well as the trust that allows people to act together to pursue common goals leading to behavioural outcomes (Coleman Citation1990; Putnam, Leonardi, and Nanetti Citation1993; Portes Citation1998). For example, levels of volunteering, membership in organisations and entertainment with friends and relatives can serve as indicators of social capital (Costa and Kahn Citation2003). Social capital is a multidimensional construct operating at community and individual levels, though it primarily displays its effects at the micro-level or scale of individuals (Sabatini and Sarracino Citation2019). Social indicators of trust operate throughout and connect the frontiers of the micro, meso and macro-levels. They can be used by individuals to appraise specific experts at the micro-level during one-on-one interactions (e.g. patient-doctor conversations). The collective experiences of lay persons can be grouped for network analysis to monitor social patterns at the meso-level (e.g. particular groups being more distrustful experts). And because social indicators inform and are informed by social, political and economic forces at the macro-level (e.g. institutional affiliation or position in a hierarchy), their ubiquity spans society.

Studies in social capital have found that in the years preceding the social networking revolution, indicators of social capital, including face-to-face interaction and social trust, had declined in many democratic countries (Putnam Citation2002; Costa and Kahn Citation2003; Sarracino Citation2010; Bartolini, Bilancini, and Pugno Citation2013). This is coupled with the finding that all forms of trust significantly decrease with participation in online networks (Sabatini and Sarracino Citation2019). In an online context, where people decide whom to trust based on second-order indicators, people are known to use the number of Twitter followers, the amount of likes a Facebook post gets, or what goes viral as indicators (however imprecise) of an expert’s influence and subsequently as a social indicator of trust.

This special issue is dedicated to broadening our understanding of trust in experts through the examination of social indicators of trust as structural and cognitive reflections of social capital. Structural social capital concerns people’s behaviours like their social participation in formal and informal interpersonal interactions. Cognitive social capital is made up of people’s perceptions and subsequent decisions to extend trust which can promote pro-social behaviour (Uphoff Citation2000). Our authors engage questions of cognition and structure by considering a broad spectrum of indicators of trust that challenge our social capacities to navigate information embedded in complex social institutions as well as our accompanying social, moral and emotional judgements. The articles in this collection begin by analyzing social indicators of trust from a theoretical perspective by questioning boundaries, investigating relationships, enabling expert-identifying mechanisms, distinguishing types of trust, finding logic in distrust and arguing for the necessity of social values. The second half the issue focuses on how indicators manifest and are applied in practice. This part begins with a historical account followed by an investigation of the structure of independent and political institutions, which brings us to a short exploration of social indicators of trust in the context of the COVID-19 pandemic.

Our theoretical discussion begins with Gloria Origgi’s work critiquing the boundary between epistemic and social trust as represented by social indicators of trust. Origgi argues that non-epistemic indicators (like reputation or values) can rationally contribute to our trustful attitudes in a reasonable way different from merely believing the truth. However, Origgi also recognizes that non-epistemic social indicators are fragile, and stresses the need to avoid particular biases when deferring to such indicators in order to decide which experts to trust.

Matthew Bennett proposes a further distinction between epistemic and recommendation trust. The major difference between the two being that one is based on belief and the other on action, the latter having more demanding conditions. In response, Bennett argues that more is needed when lay publics are asked not only to believe experts but to act on their recommendation because they need to establish whether the recommendation aligns with what is important to them.

In an examination of compatibility amongst types of trust between experts and lay publics, T.Y. Branch investigates the role and communication of values in science as social indicators of trust. By following the history of the value-free ideal in a Western context throughout science education and communication, Branch argues that this predominant ideal’s restriction and presentation of mostly epistemic values is antithetical to establishing ‘enhanced’ epistemic trust, where scientists take lay publics’ non-epistemic values into consideration in response to inductive risk.

Ben Almassi’s work engages the philosophically rich space between belief formation and testimonial utterances, emphasizing the ethics of trust realized through goodwill and responsiveness. Like many of the authors in this special issue, he avoids reducing trustworthiness to reliability, arguing that explicitly relational views are relevant for both personal relationships as well as expert trustworthiness. Almassi urges us to consider affectively positive, neutral and negative dimensions that can make a difference for expert trustworthiness.

Further in terms of expert trustworthiness, the traditional view is that status is a proxy for competence and service-oriented-intention. But under a more skeptical account, status can be seen as an indicator of collective egoism and not a sign of trustworthiness. Status distrust has in response been seen as a manifestation of irrationality. Hugh Desmond argues in favour of logical ‘status distrust’, especially as lay publics with lesser epistemic status are objectively in a more vulnerable position than those with a higher status. Desmond proposes that experts should place greater emphasis on demonstrating trustworthiness instead of taking it for granted.

To close our theoretical discussion, Charles Lassiter attributes the risk of misidentifying experts and endorsing false beliefs (at least some of the time) to the malfunctioning of culturally evolved mechanisms in faulty epistemic contexts. This can occur without lay publics actually having failed any epistemic obligations. Lassiter identifies three background conditions (success criteria, property identification and causal connection) which when satisfied, enable expert-identifying mechanisms to function properly. If any of them fail, the likelihood of identifying a non-authority as authoritative is increased.

After conceptualising the possibilities of social indicators of trust in experts, we take a more applied approach with Ákos Szegöfi and Christophe Heintz who pick-up on the importance of culturally evolved mechanisms and investigate how they can apply to institutions. Szegöfi and Heintz explore how epistemic vigilance can be outsourced in a historical context by examining newspaper presses as social institutions. They argue such institutions have evolved to assess the epistemic value of communicated information and adopt the psychological capacities of epistemic vigilance. Motivating factors for this include people’s preference for accurate and reliable information, their ability to assess these communications as well as contingent historical factors that make it worthwhile (or not) to maintain institutions of epistemic vigilance.

In a Nordic cultural context, Torbjørn Gundersen and Cathrine Holst explore how publics assess the trustworthiness of science advice mechanisms where scientists are expected to inform public policy making. Gundersen and Holst argue that the possession of relevant expertise, justified moral and political considerations, as well as proper institutional design are all conditions for trustworthy science advice. The authors conclude that science advisory committees are trusted without being entirely trustworthy, and even if science advice is not entirely trustworthy, its surroundings help to make it so.

Lastly, in a turn towards contemporary developments, we conclude with analyses of social indicators as they pertain to the work produced by scientific experts during the COVID-19 pandemic. To begin, Tarun Kattumana explores the role of social indicators with respect to vaccine hesitancy. Kattumana does this by examining how trust intersects the ‘5C model’ comprised of convenience, complacency, confidence, context, and communication. Kattumana shows that experts view the decision to vaccinate as a question of confidence in science whereas vaccine hesitant individuals see it in terms of trust. Kattumana proposes two social indicators used to assess experts in this case: (i) expert reaction to hesitant concerns and (ii) the loss of freedom in relation to vaccine requirements.

Carlo Martini, Monica Consolandi, Davide Battisti and Federico Bina investigate some of the problems that knowledge brokers face when communicating in times of crisis. For example, communicating scientific information during an emergency involves greater responsibility because of the immediate risks of communicating false positive or negative information. In a case study of Italian scientist-communicators, Martini et al. recount the experiences of scientists during the pandemic and how their role as trustworthy expert (or knowledge broker) was perceived during this exceptional time.

In conclusion, trust in experts is not blind trust. Nor is trust in experts mere reliance on epistemic credentials. Trust in experts is established through the evaluation of social information that surrounds the experts, their commitments, values, relationships, institutions and circumstance. In this sense, our evaluation of an expert is neither purely epistemic nor purely individualistic: rather it takes place in a rich social context which we are dependent on. This special issue furthers the understanding of non-experts’ decisions about whom to trust by providing an introduction on how lay publics use social indicators to trust. We do so from theoretical and practical angles as well as descriptive and normative positions. We enlarge the traditional epistemic dimensions of the expert-novice problem to capture second-order indicators of trust in order to further contextualise, and even humanize, trust in experts. Though our survey of social indicators of trust in experts could not possibly cover all relevant and deserving dimensions of study, we are confident it will spark further questions and make robust interdisciplinary connections in a communal attempt to understand how social indicators of trust can and should manifest.

Disclosure statement

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).

Additional information

Funding

This project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme under grant agreement No 870883. The information and opinions are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the opinion of the European Commission.

Notes

1. The first international academic journal Social Indicators Research published its introductory volume in 1974. The number of articles the journal publishes each year has grown almost 18 times since its debut − 18 articles were published in 1974 compared to 314 articles in 2019 (Kumar et al. Citation2022).

2. Part of what still needs to be investigated with respect to generalized trust is the unresolved ‘chicken-and-egg’ problem. Causal questions remain unanswered in most theories and empirical findings (Delhey and Newton Citation2003). In effect, whether conceptually or empirically, when we study trust and another variable, which comes first remains unclear.

3. Goldman (Citation2001) makes a distinction between exoteric statements which are accessible to lay publics and semantic/epistemic esoteric expert statements which are not accessible. Goldman also makes the assumption that most expert statements are esoteric or not accessible but notes that the epistemic status of statements can change and become accessible.

4. Anyone with thorough knowledge of the existing evidence and differing views of those in the field might also be deserving of the expert title, albeit in a weaker sense.

References

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 2011. “Democracy, Public Policy, and Lay Assessments of Scientific Testimony.” Episteme 8 (2): 144–164. doi:10.3366/epi.2011.0013.
  • Awaworyi Churchill, Sera, and Vinod Mishra. 2017. “Trust, Social Networks and Subjective Wellbeing in China.” Social Indicators Research 132 (1): 313–339. doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-015-1220-2.
  • Bäck, Maria, and Henrik Serup Christensen. 2016. “When Trust Matters—A Multilevel Analysis of the Effect of Generalized Trust on Political Participation in 25 European Democracies.” Journal of Civil Society 12) 2: 178–197. doi:10.1080/17448689.2016.1176730.
  • Baier, Annette. 1986. “Trust and Antitrust.” Ethics 96 (2): 231–260. doi:10.1086/292745.
  • Bartolini, Stefano, Ennio Bilancini, and Maurizio Pugno. 2013. “Did the Decline in Social Connections Depress Americans’ Happiness?” Social Indicators Research 110 (3): 1033–1059. doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-011-9971-x.
  • Coleman, James S. 1990. Foundations of Social Theory. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
  • Costa, Dora L., and Matthew E. Kahn. 2003. “Understanding the American Decline in Social Capital 1952–1998.” Kyklos 56 (1): 17–46. doi:10.1111/1467-6435.00208.
  • Dauner, Kim Nichols, Neil A. Wilmot, and Jennifer F. Schultz. 2015. “Investigating the Temporal Relationship Between Individual-Level Social Capital and Health in Fragile Families.” BMC Public Health 15 (1): 1130. doi:10.1186/s12889-015-2437-3.
  • Delhey, Jan, and Kenneth Newton. 2003. “Who Trusts? The Origins of Social Trust in Seven Societies.” European Societies 5 (2): 93–137. doi:10.1080/1461669032000072256.
  • Delhey, Jan, and Kenneth Newton. 2005. “Predicting Cross-National Levels of Social Trust: Global Pattern or Nordic Exceptionalism?” European Sociological Review 21 (4): 311–327. doi:10.1093/esr/jci022.
  • Douglas, Heather E. 2021. “The Role of Scientific Expertise in Democracy.” In Routledge Handbook of Political Epistemology, edited by Michael Hannon and Jeroen de Ridder, 435–455. London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780429326769-52.
  • Ferriss, Abbott L. 1988. “The Uses of Social Indicators.” Social Forces 66 (3): 601–617. doi:10.2307/2579568.
  • Fukuyama, Francis. 1995. Trust: Social Virtues and the Creation of Prosperity. New York: Free Press.
  • Gluckman, Peter, and James Wilsdon. 2016. “From Paradox to Principles: Where Next for Scientific Advice to Governments?” Palgrave Communications 2 (1): 16077. doi:https://doi.org/10.1057/palcomms.2016.77.
  • Goldman, Alvin. 2001. “Experts: Which Ones Should You Trust?” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1): 85–110. doi:10.2307/3071090.
  • Hardwig, John. 1985. “Epistemic Dependence.” The Journal of Philosophy 82 (7): 335–349. doi:10.2307/2026523.
  • Holton, Richard. 1994. “Deciding to Trust, Coming to Believe.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72 (1): 63–76. doi:10.1080/00048409412345881.
  • John, Stephen. 2020. ”The Politics of Trust.” In Trust: A Philosophical Approach, edited by Adriano Fabris, 49–61. Cham: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-44018-3_4.
  • Knack, Stephen, and Philip Keefer. 1997. “Does Social Capital Have an Economic Payoff? A Cross-Country Investigation.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 112 (4): 1251–1288. doi:10.1162/003355300555475.
  • Koskinen, Inkeri. 2020. “Defending a Risk Account of Scientific Objectivity.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 71 (4): 1187–1207. doi:10.1093/bjps/axy053.
  • Kumar, Satish, Filomena Maggino, Raj V. Mahto, Riya Sureka, Leonardo Salvatore Alaimo, and Weng Marc Lim. 2022. “Social Indicators Research: A Retrospective Using Bibliometric Analysis.” Social Indicators Research 162 (1): 413–448. doi:10.1007/s11205-021-02847-9.
  • Land, Kenneth C. 1971. “On the Definition of Social Indicators.” The American Sociologist 6 (November): 322–325.
  • Land, Kenneth C., and Alex C. Michalos. 2018. “Fifty Years After the Social Indicators Movement: Has the Promise Been Fulfilled?” Social Indicators Research 135 (3): 835–868. doi:10.1007/s11205-017-1571-y.
  • Messner, Steven F., Richard Rosenfeld, and Eric P. Baumer. 2004. “Dimensions of Social Capital and Rates of Criminal Homicide.” American Sociological Review 69 (6): 882–903. doi:10.1177/000312240406900607.
  • Nakhaie, Reza, and Robert. Arnold. 2010. “A Four Year (1996–2000) Analysis of Social Capital and Health Status of Canadians: The Difference That Love Makes.” Social Science & Medicine 71 (5): 1037–1044. doi:10.1016/j.socscimed.2010.05.033.
  • Nannestad, Peter. 2008. “What Have We Learned About Generalized Trust, if Anything?” Annual Review of Political Science 11: 413–436. doi:10.1146/annurev.polisci.11.060606.135412.
  • Origgi, G. 2004. “Is Trust an Epistemological Notion?” Episteme 1 (1): 61–72. doi:10.3366/epi.2004.1.1.61.
  • Portes, Alejandro. 1998. “Social Capital: Its Origins and Applications in Modern Sociology.” Annual Review of Sociology 24 (1): 1–24. doi:https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.soc.24.1.1.
  • Putnam, Robert D. 2000. Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community. New York: Simon & Schuster.
  • Putnam, Robert D. 2002. Democracies in Flux. The Evolution of Social Capital in Contemporary Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Putnam, Robert D., R. Leonardi, and Raffaella Y. Nanetti. 1993. Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. doi:10.2307/j.ctt7s8r7.
  • Ritzen, J., W. Easterly, and M. Woolcock. 2000. “On ‘Good’ Politicians and ‘Bad’ Policies—Social Cohesion, Institutions, and Growth.” Policy Research Working Paper no. WPS 2448. Washington, DC: World Bank.
  • Sabatini, Fabio. 2015. “Review of Immigrant Networks and Social Capital.” Journal of Economic Literature 53 (2): 371–374.
  • Sabatini, Fabio, and Francesco Sarracino. 2019. “Online Social Networks and Trust.” Social Indicators Research 142 (1): 229–260. doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-018-1887-2.
  • Sarracino, Francesco. 2010. “Social Capital and Subjective Well-Being Trends: Comparing 11 Western European Countries.” The Journal of Socio-Economics 39 (4): 482–517. doi:10.1016/j.socec.2009.10.010.
  • Sheldon, E. B., and H. E. Freeman. 1970. “Notes on Social Indicators: Promises and Potential.” Policy Sciences 1 (1): 97–111. doi:https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00145195.
  • Sperber, Dan, Fabrice Clément, Christophe Heintz, Olivier Mascaro, Hugo Mercier, Gloria Origgi, and Deirdre Wilson. 2010. “Epistemic Vigilance.” Mind & Language 25 (4): 359–393. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01394.x.
  • Sturgis, P., R. Patulny, N. Allum, and F. Buscha. 2012. “Social Connectedness and Generalized Trust: A Longitudinal Perspective.” Paper No. 2012–19. Institute for Social & Economic Research.
  • United States Department of Health, Education, and Welfare. 1969. “Toward a Social Report.” Washington, DXl: VS. Government Printing Office.
  • Uphoff, Norman. 2000. “Understanding Social Capital: Learning from the Analysis and Experience of Participation.” In Social Capital: A Multifaceted Perspective, edited by Partha Dagsgupta and Ismail Serageldin, 215–252. Washington: World Bank Publications.
  • Uslaner, Eric M. 2002. The Moral Foundations of Trust. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wilholt, Torsten. 2013. “Epistemic Trust in Science.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 64 (2): 233–253. doi:10.1093/bjps/axs007.
  • Ziersch, Anna, Frances Elaine Baum, Colin MacDougall, and Christine Putland. 2005. “Neighbourhood Life and Social Capital: The Implications for Health.” Social Science & Medicine 60 (1): 71–86. doi:10.1016/J.SOCSCIMED.2004.04.027.

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.